Even though you think and behave
perfectly normally, you might already have Alzheimer’s disease. In fact, you might warrant the
label of “pre-clinical Alzheimer’s
disease” for a full 20 years before graduating to the full-fledged condition. That according to the latest definition of Alzheimer’s put forward by
the National Institute on Aging together with Alzheimer’s Association 3 years
ago.
Heralded as a radical
departure from earlier clinical diagnostic criteria, the new definition is in
line with how we think about other chronic conditions such as cancer or heart
disease. Normal cells often mutate into cancerous cells and proliferate for a
long time before there are enough of the to produce symptoms—and a cancer
diagnosis. Plaques may be deposited in the lining of coronary arteries long
before they narrow blood vessels enough to impair blood flow to the heart
resulting in chest pain. In all these cases, the hope is that we may be able to
intervene during the pre-symptomatic phase, altering what is currently the
inevitable trajectory of illness. In the case of Alzheimer’s, detecting various
“biomarkers” in the blood or cerebrospinal fluid would signal the need for some
kind of biochemical intervention. The problem has been that we don’t as yet
have any such intervention. For now, the main purpose of early diagnosis is to
identify people who could enroll in research on the prevention of
Alzheimer’s—assuming the diagnostic techniques are sufficiently reliable and
the benefits of research outweigh the burdens of knowing what the future has in
store.
Philosopher Dena Davis makes
a different case for the value of early diagnosis in this month’s Journal of
Medical Ethics. Knowing that a person is destined to develop dementia, she
argues, is invaluable so he can kill himself.
The option of “rational
suicide,” as Davis calls it, is based on wanting to avoid becoming dependent
and on wanting to spare family the burden of caregiving, as well as the
potential loss of an inheritance. The diabolical nature of dementia is that if
you wait until you are a burden, until you can no longer do any of the
things that once gave meaning to your life, then you will most likely have reached a stage where
you have also lost the ability to take your own life or even to remember that you
ever wanted to end your life if you developed advanced dementia. And those
countries (such as Switzerland, Belgium, and the Netherlands) and those American states (Montana,
Oregon, Washington, and Vermont) where Physician Assisted Suicide (PAS) is legal all require that the
patient be of sound mind at the time the request is made and that she have a
prognosis of not more than 6 months. So PAS is not generally an option for people with
dementia.
There is a gentler
alternative to pre-emptive suicide, and that is drawing up an advance directive
that authorizes the withholding of life-prolonging medical treatment in the
event of dementia. But Davis discounts this option, claiming that courts and
ethicists increasingly dispute the right of a person, while cognitively intact,
to make any claims about the interests of his future demented self.
In fact, opponents of
pre-emptive suicide such as Rebecca Dresser, whose response to Davis appears in
the same issue of the ethics journal, say something a little different. They do
not assert, as Davis contends, that competent Jane Doe should have no say over
what happens to incompetent Jane Doe. That would make little sense as much of
the point of advance directives is to plan for possible loss of competence.
Rather, Dresser argues that “precedent autonomy,” in particular the choices
made when competent, should be tempered by considering the present interests of
demented Jane Doe. This is the dilemma of the happy dement that Dresser
addressed in an earlier article on the subject.
Suppose that today I am an
anxious, driven, competitive person. I find the prospect of being unable to
write articles or give talks or care for patients intolerable. But suppose that
one day, I do lose my ability to write articles and give talks and care for
patients. And suppose that lo and behold, I am no longer anxious or
competitive. Instead, I am relaxed and cheerful. I smile at everyone
indiscriminately. I am no longer inhibited and I clap my hands and tap my feet
to all kinds of music. I’m no longer a picky eater and instead I say everything I’m
served, no matter how bland or poorly prepared, is delicious. I don’t recognize
my children but am glad to see them, just as I’m glad to see the aide who
dresses me in the morning. Surely my best interest is in continuing to live as
long as I can remain in my current state.
The challenge, as I think
Rebecca Dresser understands and Dena Davis does not, is to balance the
perspectives of Jane-Doe-ten-years-ago and Jane-Doe-today. How should we do
this and who should be the arbiter? The way to proceed, I believe, is for
former Jane Doe to identify the goal of care for her future self. Plausible
goals are the prolongation of life, maximization of quality of life, or
promotion of comfort. Death, parenthetically, is not a goal; it is a means to an end. Only rarely is
it the only or the best means to achieving a legitimate goal. Most people, I
suspect, would choose comfort as the goal in advanced dementia and maximizing
quality of life as the goal in moderate dementia. All the physician needs to do
is to translate that goal into practice. For an acute medical problem such as
pneumonia, for example, comfort means using Tylenol to keep fever at bay and
oxygen to ameliorate shortness of breath. Maximizing quality of life may mean
using oral antibiotics—but not hospitalization in an intensive care unit with a
ventilator for breathing.
We will never entirely be able
to prevent people from committing suicide upon learning they are at substantial
risk, if they live long enough, of developing clinical Alzheimer’s. After all,
people can kill themselves when diagnosed with a disease such as metastatic cancer,
even before they develop intolerable symptoms, though few do so. They could kill themselves
prophylactically at age 65 or 70 to assure they will never get any awful
disease, though most people do not choose this route. Our responsibility, however, as clinicians, ethicists, and lawyers is
to try to make sure that every individual can live as good a life as possible,
whatever cards she has been dealt. That’s what a good society does.
No comments:
Post a Comment