Showing posts with label CPR. Show all posts
Showing posts with label CPR. Show all posts

June 20, 2018

Much Ado About CPR

Two short essays in this week’s New England Journal of Medicine present differing perspectives on how to treat a desperately ill woman w in the ICU of an American hospital, a woman who is unable to make her own decisions and has no advance directive. One author responded that the right course of action was to “institute a DNR order” and the other that it was to “continue full resuscitative measures,” setting up a quasi-debate. I say a quasi-debate because the two authors, as per the editor’s instructions, simply laid out their own arguments without responding to the other’s point of view. I know, because I am one of the two.

I asserted that the physician should declare the patient DNR—a woman with no written advance directive and no designated health care surrogate who was dying of multiple organ failure triggered by sepsis and unresponsive to maximal medical therapy. Attempted CPR in this setting, I argued, was as close to futile as medical treatment ever is; moreover, the patient had clearly stated to a friend and neighbor that she would not want aggressive measures when facing overwhelming odds. I stand by my arguments, which I won’t repeat here, but I regret that the discussion focused on the wrong question.

The wrong question is whether the patient should have a DNR status; the right question asks about the general treatment strategy rather than a specific medical intervention and about the process for deciding, not just the outcome of the process. It moves the discussion beyond considerations of futility—a debated that raged in the 1980s and ultimately led to the recognition that futility is meaningless without reference to what treatment is intended to accomplish. Maintaining a patient who is in a persistent vegetative state on artificial nutrition is futile if the goal is to restore her to full functioning as a thinking human being. But it’s entirely appropriate if the goal is to sustain life in the sense of a heart that beats and lungs that respire. Discussing how to make medical decisions for patients who have lost capacity and how to think about treatment for those who are dying allows us to discuss much more important decisions than whether or not to attempt CPR.

Ever since 1984, when a New York hospital was found guilty of putting purple dots on patients’ charts signaling that they were not to be resuscitated—without their knowledge or input or that of their next of kin—we’ve been obsessed with DNR orders. I suspect that more ink has been spilled on whether, when and why to write a DNR order than on any other medical decision. The reason, presumably, is that it seems irreversible: if a patient sustains a cardiac arrest and CPR isn’t performed, the patient will surely die. Other seemingly momentous decisions often prove not quite so momentous—even Karen Ann Quinlan, the first patient to bring the possibility of not intervening medically to public attention, lingered for nine years after her “life-sustaining” ventilator had been disconnected. A choice not to resuscitate is far more unambiguous—although CPR, it should be pointed out, is hardly a guarantee of life.

Cardiac arrest may have special cachet because it seems to divide the living from the dead. But in fact, for older patients who are critically ill, it is often merely the last step in what is often a relentless progression of markers on the way to death. From the perspective of human suffering and of doing good (and avoiding harm), other steps along the way are often far more significant. After all, a person whose heart has stopped and who is not breathing is no longer able to experience anything, neither the existential angst from awareness of imminent death nor the physical discomfort of aggressive treatment. The nurses and doctors who attempt CPR in a dying patient may feel guilty of assault; they often regard intubation, chest compressions, and electrical shocks as an undignified way to end life, but they are the ones experiencing malaise, not the patient.

Subjecting a patient who is in the final phase of life to dialysis for four hours a day, three times a week, or to major surgery to repair a damaged heart valve, or to ventilator care for advanced lung disease, by contrast, may cause pain and suffering to the person receiving treatment. Both the potential benefit of treatment (longer life) and its potential burdens (ranging from delirium and functional decline to a shorter life) are difficult to assess quantitatively. These decisions, which are difficult to make with a competent patient and correspondingly more fraught with an incapacitated patient, are the ones we should be discussing, not CPR.

Ironically, despite the now 42-year history of DNR orders, there is still confusion about whether DNR indicates that CPR will not be performed in the event of a cardiopulmonary arrest (as it is defined by the American College of Cardiology and other authorities) or something more. Indeed, the opposing piece in the New England Journal of Medicine talks about a time-limited trial of “continued resuscitative measures,” which presumably refers to ongoing ventilator treatment for respiratory failure, dialysis for kidney failure, and fluids and antibiotics for sepsis, rather than for a few minutes of attempted CPR. This uncertainty about what DNR means reflects another problem with the obsession with “getting the DNR order,” and that is the widespread belief that treatment decisions must be all-or-nothing: if you don’t want CPR, then surely you don’t want any potentially life-prolonging medical interventions. The reality is that many people don’t want burdensome treatments that are extremely unlikely to be beneficial, but that doesn’t mean they want to focus exclusively on comfort. 

There’s much more to discuss—I haven’t even touched on the process for making medical decisions. That includes not only who the surrogate should be in the event of decisional incapacity and what standard that surrogate should use for making decisions (substituted judgment is the usual standard, with best interests the back-up if no information about the patient’s preferences is available), but also how the discussion should unfold. Typically, physicians are so eager to reach a decision about what to do that they jump to this step in the process without first clarifying the patient’s underlying health state (in the NEJM vignette, the crucial bit of information is that the patient was dying), as though preferences are independent of any broader context. But for now, let me leave you with the thought that both medical decision-making and advance care planning involve much more than checking off items on a menu, and that if we do engage in intervention-specific planning, CPR should be low on the list of what we discuss.

February 19, 2018

Good for Nothing?

               For over thirty years, we’ve been arguing about when medical care is “futile.” The debate began in the 1980s, when the most common question faced by hospital ethics committee stopped being, “do doctors have to do this procedure, even if patients or their families don’t want it?” to “do doctors have to do this procedure if patients or their families demand it, even if the doctors don’t want to?” One case that attracted a great deal of attention was that of Helga Wanglie, a woman in her late eighties who was in a vegetative state after hip surgery and whose physicians wanted a “DNR” order. Helga’s husband, speaking on her behalf, disagreed. Ultimately, the case ended up in the Minnesota courts and was settled based on a technicality—the hospital sued on the grounds that the husband wasn’t an acceptable surrogate, but the court found that he was. The issue of what qualified as “futile” treatment was largely skirted.
         The bioethics community then struggled to define futility, with Schneiderman, Jecker, and Johnson proposing what appeared to be a quantitative definition: if the treatment in question has failed in the last 100 cases, then it’s futile. There were several problems with this approach. First, it sounds nice and scientific, but nobody was collecting data on what worked in whom. Even if we had information about 100 people, they were rarely identical in what might be crucial ways—is an 85-year-old with advanced dementia, diabetes, and heart disease who has a cardiac arrest equivalent to a 75-year-old with cancer? Secondly, what exactly was meant by a treatment “failing?” Helga Wanglie’s doctors said a ventilator was “failed” treatment because it could not restore the patient to her condition before she was hospitalized—it wasn’t going to allow her to walk out of the hospital and go home. Her husband said a ventilator was “successful” treatment because it sustained Helga’s life. The answer to whether a treatment would be futile turned out to be, “it depends.” It depends on what the treatment was supposed to accomplish. The net effect was that in most of the country, the word “futility” was abandoned in discussing treatment options.
         The exception was Texas, which passed an “Advance Directives Act” in 1999, widely known as the Texas “Futile Care Law.” It spells out a process by which physicians can assert that a treatment is futile and need not be given, as well as a process for adjudicating any disputes between physicians, patients, and families. Ultimately, the physicians have the final say.
         Despite the consensus in the bioethics community and the near consensus among state legislatures that discussing futility was unhelpful, physicians have continued to believe that various treatments should not be provided in certain circumstances because it is morally wrong. To address the persistent discomfort physicians and nurses have felt administering what they regard as “futile” care, the American Thoracic Society recently came out with a position paper called “Responding to Requests for Potentially Inappropriate Treatment inIntensive Care Units.” This policy statement was endorsed by four other professional organizations. Another guideline, this one published by the Society for Critical Care Medicine, addressed what it called “non-beneficial” treatment. The originators of the quantitative futility concept, Schneiderman, Jecker, and Jonsen, continue to believe that “futility” is the best way to describe the class of treatments under consideration.
         So, which is it: Futile treatment? Potentially inappropriate treatment? Non-beneficial treatment? None of the above?
         The issue, it seems to me, is whether the problem is fundamentally a technical one or an ethical one. “Futility” advocates want to define the problem (perhaps surprisingly, since its principal supporters are ethicists) as a technical one. The proponents of “potentially inappropriate care” seem to acknowledge that the issue is ethical (again surprisingly, since its main advocates are physicians). It would be lovely to make the dilemma vanish with a technical solution! If only we could state precisely when CPR or a ventilator or dialysis or chemotherapy cannot work to achieve whatever specific goal it is supposed to accomplish. Then we wouldn’t have to ask whether it’s the right approach. Surely, we can all agree that if something cannot work, like antibiotics for a viral infection or apricot pits for cancer, providing such a “remedy” is inconsistent with professional standards. 
           Unfortunately, such cases of what has been called “physiologic futility” are relatively rare. More common is the situation where an intervention is deemed by medical professionals to be inappropriate because, in their estimation, the burdens outweigh the benefits. This conclusion rests on an understanding of the clinical situation, but also on a moral judgment.
         The desire to convert what is quintessentially an ethical dilemma to a technical one is understandable. It relies in large measure on the recognition that many medical decisions do have a technical and an ethical component, and that often, it is up to the patient (or the patient’s surrogate) to address the ethical piece. But that awareness does not preclude professional ethical standards playing a role as well. The debate about physician assisted suicide, while complicated because of varying legal standards, is to a large extent about whether physicians regard ending the life of a suffering, terminally ill patient as consistent with their ethical norms. The widespread recognition of the responsibility of physicians to care for patients who are criminals or other individuals they may find personally objectionable is based on the ethical code of conduct of the medical profession.
         Recognizing the patient’s values and shaping medical care to be consistent with those values is desirable—when the patient’s ethics and those of the medical profession do not irreconcilably conflict. It’s important to point out that I’m not just talking about the idiosyncratic views of a given physician—the personal ethical values that have been put forward as a justification for failing to provide contraception. I’m talking about an ethical standard of care set by the profession as a whole. The American Thoracic Society statement on “potentially inappropriate care,” while not perfect, is an effort to define what the profession regards as appropriate—acknowledging, through its caveat about “potentially inappropriate” care, that there could occasionally be circumstances where the profession’s norm is not applicable.


July 05, 2015

Shocking News

Much has been written lately about over-treatment of older patients. Only rarely does anyone suggest that older patients are getting too little treatment, but a new study in JAMA does just that. The reality isn't quite so clear.

The treatment is the implantable cardioverter defibrillator (ICD) and the patients are people over the age of 65 who have had a heart attack and are found afterwards to have a weak heart (defined as an ejection fraction less or equal to 35%). These patients are at risk of sudden death, of an irregular heart rhythm such as ventricular tachycardia, and the ICD is designed to deliver an electric shock if that happens, effectively bringing the patients back from death. By looking at the National Cardiovascular Data Registry, which keeps track of heart attack patients, the authors of the article found that only 8.1% of “eligible” patients actually received an ICD. As a result, they claim, the 92% of patients who didn’t get an ICD were more likely to die than their counterparts who did.

This is a surprising finding in light of the persuasive and cogent argument made by Sharon Kaufman in her recent book, Ordinary Medicine: Extraordinary Treatments, Longer Lives, and Where To Draw The Line. Kaufman makes the case that many high tech treatments come to be seen by physicians and patients as normal and necessary once Medicare agrees to pay for them. The end result for many marginally beneficial, burdensome, and expensive treatments, including the ICD, is that patients just can’t say no. If that's true, why are so few older people getting an ICD? 

Now it wouldn't be the first time that ageism or misinformation prevented older people from getting beneficial treatment. Many years ago, patients who were over a certain age were precluded from receiving clot-busting drugs (thrombolytic therapy) because it was widely assumed that in older age groups, the risks outweighed the benefits. It turned out that clot-busting drugs were actually more beneficial in older patients, basically because their heart disease tended to be severe which meant they stood to gain a great deal from treatment. Elevated systolic blood pressure was likewise once assumed to be normal in the geriatric population, or even desirable in order to improve blood flow to the brain. Studies eventually showed that elevated systolic blood pressure, even in older patients, predisposed to stroke and other unfortunate outcomes, and warranted treatment—though the recommendations about just how much blood pressure should be lowered have evolved over time. Is the ICD implantation rate just another case of bias or ignorance at work?

Dr. Robert Hauser of the Minnesota Heart Institute, writing an editorial published alongside this article, blames our fragmented health care system. He speculates that primary care physicians may not realize that their patients were supposed to get an ICD. The fact that there's supposed to be a 40-day waiting period between the onset of the heart attack and implantation of the ICD contributes to the problem. Hauser suggests that the primary care physician is so frazzled and overburdened that he is apt to neglect to send his patient to a cardiologist. Is this the explanation?



It can’t be the whole story. While patients who saw a cardiologist after hospital discharge were more likely to wind up with an ICD than patients who didn’t, only 30% of the patients who saw a cardiologist had an ICD implanted. Recall that 100% of them were, technically speaking, “candidates” for an ICD. So what else is going on?

Hauser hints at another explanation: “It is possible that some older patients may refuse ICD treatment for personal reasons or because comorbidities such as endstage kidney disease or advanced frailty were considered in the decision regarding ICD implantation.” He doesn't accept this explanation as sufficient, rightly recognizing that patients are very likely to accept whatever technological intervention their physician recommends and that shared decision-making, if it takes place at all, is apt to reflect the physician’s preferences as well as the patient’s. So the problem, if it is a problem, must lie with doctors, too. Physicians are not systematically and emphatically recommending ICD implantation to their older patients. Even the most technologically sophisticated academic medical centers only implanted ICDs in 16% of their eligible older patients. But is this a problem that needs fixing, like under-treatment of heart attacks with clot busters and inadequate treatment of high blood pressure in the past?

Dr.  Hauser believes it is, saying “even though the use of ICD for primary prevention may not seem to make as much sense for an 80 year old patient as it does for a patient in his 50s or 60s, an older patient at risk for sudden cardiac death should have the same opportunity to choose potentially lifesaving therapy.” But the benefits of ICD in those over 80 are far from clear. The studies include very few people in this age group. What data there is indicates that there is little if any survival benefit. Moreover, ICDs implanted in older people fire erroneously half the time. That means they deliver a very unpleasant electric shock to the hapless patient. In addition, if the ICD does work as intended, what that means is the abolition of sudden death. 

Maybe, just maybe, the low rate of ICD implantation in older people is a refreshing instance of massive civil disobedience—of both patients and doctors refusing to abide by prevailing clinical guidelines. We all have to die of something. An ICD virtually guarantees that the something will involve a protracted period of decline and suffering. If you had to choose between cancer, Alzheimer’s disease, and sudden death, which would you pick?

February 03, 2014

Pulling the Plug on DNR Orders

Recently, a friend commented that she was not sure whether or not to agree to a “DNR order” for her 90 year-old mother. Her mother has dementia and lives in a nursing home; she is her mom’s health care proxy. Complicating her decision was the knowledge that her mother had chosen a DNR status when she was cognitively intact, but then reversed her decision at the time of acute illness, believing that “DNR” meant she would not receive vigorous treatment for medical problems such as an infection or congestive heart failure. My friend told me she believed the purpose of a DNR order was to avoid a protracted, painful death and that DNR was synonymous with comfort care. 

The truth is that DNR means “do not perform CPR”—the “R” in DNR refers to resuscitation, which is shorthand for “cardiopulmonary resuscitation.” CPR is a procedure intended to counteract a cardiac arrest—the sudden cessation of the heart beat and of breathing. CPR involves administering electric shocks and, more often than not, providing artificial respiration, usually through a breathing machine (ventilator). In principle, DNR or, as it should more properly be called, since there is only a small chance that CPR will actually succeed in restoring cardiac function, DNAR (do not attempt resuscitation) refers only to what will or will not be done if the heart stops beating and breathing ceases. It has no implication for any other form of treatment. But nearly 40 years after the first DNR orders were written in hospitals, confusion about their meaning persists.

It’s not just patients and families who are confused: physicians are confused as well. I just read Sheri Fink’s book, Five Days at Memorial: Life and Death in a Storm-Ravaged Hospital, in which the triage decisions made during Hurricane Katrina included placing patients with a DNR order at the bottom of the evacuation list. Reportedly, physicians at Memorial thought that patients could have a DNR order only if they were terminally ill, which is false: a patient can elect a DNR order whenever the burdens of CPR are felt to outweigh the benefits, or if CPR is thought to be extremely unlikely to succeed--regardless of the underlying medical condition. When it looked as though not all of Memorial Hospital’s patients were going to be evacuated, it was the DNR cases who were to be left behind, sedated so as to ease their allegedly inevitable and imminent deaths.

And it’s not just in the midst of a disaster that physicians mistake “DNR” for “Do Not Treat.” Study after study has shown that physicians say they would not administer a whole variety of treatments to patients who are DNR. One representative study of 241 physicians found that they were far less likely to agree to transfer a patient to the intensive care unit or even to perform simple tests such as drawing blood. 

Most recently, physicians and nurses caring for pediatric patients also told interviewers that in practice, DNR means far more than just do not perform CPR. In this survey of 107 pediatricians and 159 pediatric nurses in a hospital setting, 67% believed a DNR order only applies to what to do after a cardiac arrest—but 33% said it implied other limitations. And 52% said that once a DNR order is in place,  a whole host of diagnostic and therapeutic interventions should be withdrawn, over and beyond CPR, and a small but disturbing minority, 6%, said that a DNR order means that comfort measures only are to be provided. 

Why, so many years after the concept of DNR was introduced, does it remain so problematic? I think both patients and physicians implicitly recognize that asking about CPR is simply the wrong question—that’s why they assume DNR refers to so much more than what doctors should do if the heart stops beating. The right question has to do with figuring out what it is that medical treatment is supposed to achieve. Is it prolonging life at any cost? Is it providing comfort and dignity? Or is it something in between, preserving those basic functions such as walking and talking and seeing and hearing that a person values most? Only after defining the overall goal of care does it make sense to focus on delineating the specific treatments that are most consistent with achieving those goals. 

An enormous amount of energy and ink have been squandered on debating about cardiopulmonary resuscitation, one of many possible medical treatments that seeks to achieve one of several possible medical goals. Maybe it’s time to pull the plug on DNR orders, banning them unless there is first a conversation about the overall direction of medical care. 

One approach to doing exactly this is POLST, Physician Orders for Life-Sustaining Treatment or, as it is called in some states, Medical Orders for the Scope of Treatment. This is a medical order, just like an order a doctor writes in a hospital for antibiotics or for blood tests; it is not just a wish statement about future care. It includes a list of specific interventions that a prospective patient has agreed are undesirable under any circumstances, and often includes CPR along with other treatments such as dialysis or artificial nutrition. But before a physician and patient agree on such an order, a conversation is supposed to take place about the goals of medical care. The problem is that it's far from clear that patients and doctors are having those discussions. They may simply be jumping to the final step, writing that order. POLST is a promising development, but only if at least as much time is spent on talking about the big picture as on its implementation.