In an op-ed in the New York Times this week, my fellow
Harvard physicians Pamela Hartzband and Jerome Groopman argue that it’s
pernicious to reward physicians for meeting quality standards. These measures
of performance, they say, are “population-based and generic, and do not take
into account the individual characteristics and preferences of the patient or
differing expert opinions on optimal practice.” Really? Are there no practices that physicians should
routinely follow if they are to practice good medicine?
The answer revolves
around the concept of “preference sensitive care,” articulated by Jack Wennberg
and Elliott Fisher of the Dartmouth Center for the Evaluative Clinical
Sciences. Preference-sensitive care
involves treatments that involve significant tradeoffs affecting the quality
and or length of life. It is contrasted with effective care, which involves essentially uncontroversial
treatments that are unambiguously optimal, or for which there are no viable
alternatives. What Hartzband and Groopman are arguing is that essentially all care is preference-sensitive and
there is no such thing as effective care. Therefore, they conclude, there is no
way that we can legitimately grade treatment as inherently good or bad—it
either reflects patients’ wishes—or physicians’ recommendations—or it doesn’t.
The view that there
are no medical practices that
constitute “effective care” and that all medical
care is preference-sensitive strikes me as profoundly misguided. In 2003, RAND
evaluated the quality of medical care in the US and found that only 55% of adult
patients surveyed by telephone had received recommended medical treatment. These treatments included counseling on smoking cessation to patients who had had
heart attacks and long-acting inhalers for people with chronic asthma. Did
the 45% of patients who did not get standard treatment actually receive care that, while not consistent with expert
recommendations, conformed well to their preferences? Could 45% of physicians
have deliberately and thoughtfully chosen a course that deviated from expert
recommendations because they had unique insight about what was best for their
patients? Is there a plausible reason why physicians should not advise cardiac
patients to stop smoking or patients with at least moderately severe asthma to
use inhalers? I doubt it.
What about older
people? Perhaps this is one population where most treatment is
preference-sensitive. After all, as I have often argued in this blog, what
makes sense for people who are frail, dying, or have dementia depends heavily
on their goals of care. Even a seemingly clear-cut decision such as whether to
have surgery for a broken hip might have a values component. A patient who is
dying, for example, and whose only goal
of care is his comfort, might choose to have bed rest and pain medication
rather than the rigors of surgery. So are there quality indicators, those
“metrics” that Hartzband and Groopman vilify, that apply to the
geriatric population?
I looked at the most
recent HEDIS (Healthcare Effectiveness Data and Information Set) measures, the
set of indicators used by health insurance companies throughout the US to
evaluate physician performance. These were designed by the NCQA (National
Committee for Quality Assurance), a non-profit, non-governmental, independent
body that relies on expert judgment and public feedback to determine quality
indicators. It turns out that there are 5 HEDIS measures for older adults, addressing
physical activity, pneumococcal vaccination, osteoporosis testing, medication
management, and fall risk management.
The 5 domains were
chosen for good reason. Physical activity plays a role in maintaining physical
function as well as in staving off depression, cardiovascular disease, and other
chronic illnesses common in old age.
Pneumonia is very
common in the elderly and it’s a killer. When it doesn’t kill, it causes
shortness of breath and confusion, often resulting in hospitalization, and may
trigger other conditions such as a heart attack. Osteoporosis is responsible
for tremendous suffering, mainly in the form of pain and impaired mobility, and
predisposes to fractures. Falls, like osteoporosis, are the cause of an
enormous amount of misery in old age. Nobody, and I mean nobody, wants to fall, just as nobody wants to
have osteoporosis. Medications are commonly used by older people—on average,
they take about 5 prescription drugs—and the more medications a person takes,
the greater the likelihood of side effects.
If the targets are
reasonable, are the specific quality indicators themselves? In general, the
answer is yes. The pneumonia metric, for example, looks at the percentage of
adults 65 and older who report ever having received a pneumococcal vaccination.
The only people for whom getting a pneumonia shot doesn’t make much sense are
those who are dying. And even patients who are dying presumably weren’t dying a
year or two years ago, at which point they should have gotten immunized against
pneumonia. Since the measure asks if a person has ever been vaccinated, the
only older patients for whom this is inappropriate are those who develop a
lethal illness at age 65 or those who regard life as worse than death (usually
also people with a fatal illness) and who hope they will get pneumonia. There
will always be people who refuse the shot out of a misguided belief that it
will cause them harm. Some people will have religious objections—though I have
yet to find an established religion that forbids vaccination (the exception is Christian Scientists but they aren’t likely to go to doctors in the first place). So physicians will rarely achieve a score of 100% on
the vaccination metric. But the question is not whether vaccination can always
be achieved; it’s whether vaccinating against pneumonia constitutes good
medical practice.
It would be nice to have separate measures for
patients who are near the end of life,
for those who meet the criteria for enrollment in hospice (whether they have
chosen to enroll or not). At the very least, for patients with a limited life
expectancy, the physician should be able to indicate that the quality
indicators are “not applicable.” But apart from this concern, the quality measures strike me, on balance, as entirely reasonable.
No comments:
Post a Comment